Catch up on stories from the past week (and beyond) at the Slashdot story archive

 



Forgot your password?
typodupeerror

Comment Re:Off Insulin onto immunosuppressants for life... (Score 4, Informative) 65

I agree that this therapy is not without significant risks, so it's not to be taken lightly.

That said, the long-term health outcomes of T1DM are also significant. So the way I see this development is that it is one more step on the path toward finding a durable, safe, and effective cure. And if approved, it may offer some patients another choice, one that of course should involve an informed discussion with competent healthcare providers.

It's important to keep in mind that healthcare is not a "one size fits all" thing. Two patients that have the same condition can respond very differently to the same therapy. Before the discovery of insulin, diabetics literally just...died. So on the path to understanding this relationship between the individual patient and the selected therapy, medical science can only offer a range of treatment options. At one time, humans believed in bloodletting, lobotomies, and arsenic to treat various illnesses. We built leper colonies. And in some places in the world, menstruation is still considered "dirty." We have made many advances, but there are still many more to be discovered.

Comment Yet another Register hit piece (Score 4, Interesting) 240

I'd rather use a slower browser that honors the user's choice of extensions--in particular those that block malicious content and privacy-violating advertising trackers--than an ostensibly faster browser that is created by a company whose entire business model is to gather as much tracking data about you in order to sell it to advertisers.

There are alternatives to both Firefox and Chrome. But choosing to use Chrome because Firefox isn't perfect is either the height of idiocy, or being paid to promote Google products.

Comment Re:Phase I is not enough. (Score 4, Insightful) 40

Birth defects due to thalidomide approval outside of the US were extensive, and you conveniently ignore this. That wasn't some media psyop: 20000 affected embryos for a drug marketed to prevent morning sickness is not something to trivialize, and the fact that it was not approved in the US meant that many American families were spared this horror.

It's ironic that you mention Type I and Type II errors, yet conclude--without any apparent consideration of such errors as they apply to the establishment of efficacy and safety--that somehow "Montana has the right idea." How would they have the right idea if anyone can choose to receive unapproved drugs before any data collection and statistical analysis is performed? That to me suggests you don't have the faintest clue about what a Type I error means.

Comment Re:Phase I is not enough. (Score 3, Informative) 40

This is a horrible plan on so many levels.

An investigational treatment that has passed Phase I only has the most basic pharmacokinetic and safety data gathered. There's virtually no efficacy data. The layman who thinks that patients with serious and unmet medical needs should have access to such treatments before efficacy is established, believes so because "what other options do they have?" Their logic is that they should be "free" to try anything.

But the primary reason why this logic is flawed is because a very high proportion of treatments at this stage of clinical development are inadequate--they are either ineffective or unsafe, or both. The second reason--one that never crosses the layman's mind--is that providing such early access would cripple trial enrollment. If even one state passes legislation to circumvent regulatory oversight, then patients will simply demand access through that state, rather than enroll in a trial and deal with the burden of following the trial protocol and procedures. And this will absolutely cause statistical and ethical problems with analyzing efficacy and safety in a trial context. The result will be either a serious delay in securing marketing approval for therapies that do succeed, or even worse, pharmaceutical companies will simply sidestep the regulatory process entirely and just start make marketing claims for untested compounds. After all, why bother spending hundreds of millions of dollars on a development program to secure approval if one state lets people try whatever they want?

One more comment: drug companies do have a pathway for patients in dire need. It's called "compassionate use" or "expanded access." So it's not like there's a brick wall preventing patients from accessing investigational therapies when they do not meet the inclusion criteria for a trial. But opening the floodgates is going to hurt way more people than it might help.

Comment Re:Model Collapse (Score 1) 98

This is exactly correct, and it also furnishes a rebuttal against the claim that AI generated "art" is not theft any more than it would be theft for a human to study, learn from, and draw upon the works of other humans. If that were true, these models would not need to be trained on original, real-world data--it could simply train itself. But model collapse is very real, and the desire of companies to steal original content from its creators by any means possible amounts to a tacit admission that the output is neither original nor on equal footing with the human-created data it was trained on.

Yes, the output can be impressive; it can mimic or even surpass human-created work in some ways. It can be incredibly useful and meaningful. But that is only because it was trained on data that had those properties to begin with. Existing AI models are not truly creative in nature, and the inability to self-train is proof.

Comment Re:Oh Jesus Christ (Score 3, Interesting) 302

I'm sick of paying for redundant federal workers, every one of which thinks their job is irreplaceable simply because managers have never been under pressure to do more with less.

It's remarkable how confidently sweeping statements are made about organizations, especially by those with little to no understanding of how they actually function. But sure, keep believing the narrative.

Comment Too speculative to be meaningful (Score 2) 209

I am dismayed that a virologist would say such things, as I would expect them to know better. The truth is that we simply do not know. There is insufficient evidence to predict whether or not the current human population has any clinically significant immunity to this H5N1 subtype. We do not even know whether or not it will mutate to become more transmissible from human to human.

Yes, there are some basic principles at work that might suggest that preexisting infections and vaccinations for human influenza could confer some degree of protection. But that's such a broad and superficial notion--it doesn't convey any sense of the extent of protection, if any. The 1918 flu pandemic ("Spanish flu") that killed millions of people, of course did not occur in a totally immunologically naive population with respect to human influenza, so what justifies any assertion that our existing exposure to human influenza will confer protection against H5N1 in any meaningful way?

In any population there will be intrinsic variability in which some people will be more susceptible to worse clinical outcomes, and others who will be less susceptible. We do not yet know who these people are, because this disease is not yet pandemic or endemic. We still don't even know who these people are for COVID-19, which has become endemic. I would have thought that especially among the scientifically literate, people would have learned something from the COVID-19 pandemic with respect to making predictions or assertions about the behavior and impact of infectious diseases on a population. I've long since given up on the general population learning anything. But I am deeply disappointed that a virologist would speculate on such matters, as the message inevitably becomes further distorted by journalists and then politicized and warped beyond all recognition by a self-absorbed and uneducated public.

Comment So what is the proposed mechanism? (Score 4, Interesting) 130

If there is evidence for association or a dose-response relationship, then what is the underlying causal mechanism? That's the real question. Alcohol consumption has other health effects, many of which are detrimental. So before this research can be considered useful, it has to explain what is happening at a metabolic level; e.g., what is alcohol consumption doing to lipoprotein synthesis or endogenous cholesterol.

Comment Re:Can we cure dementia first (Score 1) 80

But I'm not addressing the amyloid hypothesis or even Alzheimer's dementia specifically. Rather, I'm speaking more broadly about the relationship between the biological aging process, chronological age, and diseases associated with these.

You are correct that, despite the likely validity of the amyloid hypothesis, treatments that target amyloid burden do not stop disease progression, and at best seem to only buy a little more time. Such drugs were approved under questionable circumstances (notably, Biogen's aducanumab) and in my opinion, their evidence of efficacy remains weak. As yet we do not have a complete understanding of Alzheimer's pathophysiology, let alone an understanding of how age-related decline in health is related to the risk of developing cognitive impairment, dementia, or other diseases in general.

That said, my original point is that we do not necessarily need to have such an understanding in order to target mechanisms of aging. We do not need to "solve the problem of dementia" before addressing aging and longevity. They aren't mutually exclusive. If we can improve health span through improving life span, it is reasonable to predict that the onset of age-related diseases could be delayed, leading to functional extension of healthy years of life and an improvement in the quality of life for a majority of the population.

A loose analogy would be cancer research: we can research ways of stopping people who are diagnosed with various cancers from disease progression, increasing their overall survival and improving their quality of life after diagnosis. Or we can also research ways to PREVENT people from developing cancer in the first place--reducing the risk of aggressive cancers or delaying the median age at onset. These are both valid and important research activities that make a meaningful difference, and they are not mutually exclusive. That's why I object to the statement by the grandparent post that asked if we can we cure dementia first before first extending the human lifespan. It's the wrong way to think about these issues because it is quite possible that longevity research could have positive effects on the incidence and onset of dementia, as well as a whole host of other age-related diseases.

Comment Re:Can we cure dementia first (Score 2) 80

I think everyone can agree that as we age, the risk of various forms of dementia increases. But what is not as clear is whether that risk is correlated to chronological age, or whether senescence and dementia are merely the consequences of underlying inflammatory and/or epigenetic processes that can be modified.

In plain English, we have to distinguish between associations versus cause and effect. Age and dementia are associated. But maybe old age is not a CAUSE of dementia. It's possible that if we find a way to slow the aging process, the mechanism by this happens might also slow the same processes that impact cognitive decline and dementia risk. In other words, what if by increasing lifespan, we are also delaying the onset of a whole host of other diseases--diabetes, cardiovascular disease, cancer, and dementia? Your post implies that you're conceptualizing lifespan extension as adding on extra years at the end. But maybe lifespan extension is more like taking those years of healthy life and making them last longer from a biological perspective. We don't know if it's possible or what form lifespan extension will take. But that neither implies the latter nor the former. Without research, we will never know.

Comment Re: What's next? (Score 3, Insightful) 52

But it is relevant because that's exactly what's happening in real life right now.

The issue here isn't simply about the legal framework or copyright. What I'm trying to bring to light with this particular scenario are the downstream effects of current practice. The proliferation of generative AI models is significantly disruptive to a segment of creators who, whether or not they are in principle protected legally, have their livelihoods threatened. Attempts to adapt their work product are temporary solutions at best, and the actual reputational damage remains unaddressed. And while this sort of thing has happened well before such generative AIs were available, one certainly must admit that the scope of the problem has dramatically increased because of it.

So what I guess I'm saying is that even if we come to some kind of agreement about the responsible use of generative AI models (in the sense of operating within some agreed upon legal framework for the protection of intellectual property rights), there is still this gap--even by your own admission, "style" is not copyrightable--through which creators still may suffer and be discouraged to create because their own output has been leveraged against them to diminish the value of not only extant works, but future works.

In an ideal world, we wouldn't need to tie the creative process to an economic livelihood. People would create and discover and invent purely for the joy of it, without needing to attach economic value to those products in order to feed, clothe, and house themselves. But we live in a world where entities with far more money and power are able to take the creative output of others and profit off of it without consequences. And this has been true since before AI, but AI has made this malfeasance far easier and more efficient to perpetrate. The AI companies themselves admit that they need more data to train their models, and that the training off its own output is self-corrupting. This suggests to me that, at present, the original work is what principally has value, hence should receive commensurate compensation. Therefore, what such models generate is not the same as what humans do when they learn and create, because if the model could do it, they wouldn't need to train off human-created data.

Comment Re:What's next? (Score 1) 52

But the AI companies aren't buying the content in the first place. They took it without compensation to the original creators, and the proposal in question is to grant them a license to do this without any compensation unless the creator locates each AI company to opt out. And the reason why they want it structured this way is because AI companies know that if they have to pay for content up front, they couldn't afford to do it. So they take it.

The way they're getting around this issue now is shifting the responsibility onto social media and internet companies, who have updated their Terms of Service to sell the data that users submit to their sites to these AI companies, often retroactively. Original works that you never consented to be used in this manner are then being used to train AI models. You weren't compensated, but the companies get all the billions. Their defense? You contributed for free, so you gave them a license for perpetual use. So you decide not to use those sites anymore, but they already have your data. They're never going to then dig through those models and decide to pay you royalties for it, even though they sell subscriptions to use their models.

Is that fair?

Comment Re:What's next? (Score 1) 52

Here's another, more realistic scenario, one that is actually very much what is going on with generative AI.

I have a friend who is a talented artist. His works are made digitally, but he is classically trained. He doesn't have a social media presence, but he sells his work to others who commission him after finding his work through word of mouth. So, he is compensated for the art that he does create for others--essentially, a work-for-hire arrangement.

Those who commission him are avid social media users. One day, his work goes viral because of his distinctive art style. Since the terms of service of the various social media sites state that any content uploaded may be used to train generative AI models, those reposts of his work find their way into the training datasets of subscription generative AI services. Users of those services discover they can generate numerous similar artworks--in fact, almost indistinguishable from genuine originals--for a fraction of the cost and time. The AI company makes money from the subscriptions. The social media companies make money from advertisers and from selling training data to the AI company. Demand for my friend's hand-drawn (albeit digital) work dies out. He is no longer able to make a living from his artwork. He never consented to his work being included in those models. He was compensated for the original works, but nobody wants them anymore because anyone can generate thousands of similar works from models trained on those originals.

Not to be discouraged, my friend changes their style. Perhaps he even ventures into other forms of art entirely--say, sculpture or other physical media. But the cycle repeats in one form or another. Even worse, the AI models, trained on so much data, become so convincing that scammers use it to flood the internet with generated images of his style of sculpture or physical artworks. Nobody can tell whether they are real or fake. People lose significant sums of money to buy what they think are real works. Because there is so much distrust about their authenticity, demand for his work declines.

Is this fair? How do you propose this issue be solved?

Comment Re:What's next? (Score 1) 52

Honest question, because I actually don't know how to address this scenario in a fair way. To be clear, I'm asking not to make a point but because I truly do not know and would like to hear your thoughts.

Suppose someone is a struggling artist/writer/inventor/creator, toiling in relative obscurity. Their work has value but is largely unrecognized, for one reason or another. They do not have money to bring attention to their works.

Decades later, their work is suddenly "discovered" by a large corporation. Maybe that corporation found this work through a large-scale search. They leverage and monetize the original work in its complete and original entirety, but its creator gets nothing (for instance, because of some time limit expired, or maybe simply because the corporation decided the risk of any legal consequences was minimal due to the creator not having resources to protect their claim to ownership). The corporation and its shareholders become immensely wealthy as a result--say, hundreds of billions of dollars. They use this money to convince governments to change intellectual property law and locate other creations to monetize.

What recourse does the creator have? Does the creator have any right to compensation? If so, how much, and under what framework would you propose to enforce those rights?

Yes, the example is contrived. But not entirely so. After all, there are numerous historical examples of individuals who never lived to benefit from their contributions to society. I think we can all agree that's unfortunate. But as I stated at the beginning, how do we determine what is "fair," and how do we enforce that fairness? I don't know.

Slashdot Top Deals

The trouble with doing something right the first time is that nobody appreciates how difficult it was.

Working...